What is the value of philosophy? In response
to reductive pragmatic critiques of philosophy (“what’s all that insulated
ivory-tower hyper-reflective self-indulgence good for?”), here is Aristotle’s
deliberation from the Nichomachean Ethics – which I found surprisingly agreeable
and unsurprisingly superior to my own deliberations. It is an important
reminder to all those who are subject to apocalyptic self-doubt, as I am, in
regards to the worth of pure thinking (called
various things by Aristotle, including 'intellectual virtue', 'prudence' and
'wisdom', all of which have more specific content). Interestingly, his argument
is not the standard, "because without thinking we would never know what
the good is in the first place."
It is more slippery. Take note.
The Critique:
Here an objection may
be raised. “What is the use of the intellectual virtues?” it may be asked.
“Wisdom does not consider what tends to make man happy (because it is not
concerned with any kind of process). Prudence indeed does this, but why do we
need it? Prudence is the faculty which deals with what is just and noble and
good for man, i.e. with those things which it is the part of
the good man to do; but the knowledge of them no more makes us apter to do
them, if (as has been said) the [moral] virtues are habits, than it does in the
case of what is healthy and wholesome—healthy and wholesome, that is, not in
the sense of conducing to, but in the sense of issuing from, a healthy habit;
for a knowledge of medicine and gymnastics does not make us more able to do
these things.
“But if it be meant
that a man should be prudent, not in order that he may do these acts, but in
order that he may become able to do them, then prudence will be no use to those
who are good, nor even to those who are not. For it will not
matter whether they have prudence themselves, or take the advice of others who
have it. It will be enough to do in these matters as we do in regard to health;
for if we wish to be in health, we do not go and learn medicine.
“Again, it seems to
be a strange thing that prudence, though inferior to wisdom, must yet govern
it, since in every field the practical faculty bears sway and issues orders.”
Aristotle’s Rebuttal:
We must now discuss
these points; for hitherto we have been only stating objections.
First, then, we may
say that both prudence and wisdom must be desirable in themselves, since each
is the virtue of one of the parts of the soul, even if neither of them produces
anything.
Next, they do produce
something.
On the one hand,
wisdom produces happiness, not in the sense in which medicine produces health,
but in the sense in which health produces health; that is to say, wisdom
being a part of complete virtue, its possession and exercise make a man happy.
On the other hand [in
the sphere of action], man performs his function perfectly when he acts in
accordance with both prudence and moral virtue; for while the latter ensures
the rightness of the end aimed at, the former ensures the rightness of the
means thereto.
The fourth part
of the soul, the vegetative part, or the faculty of nutrition, has no analogous
excellence; for it has no power to act or not to act.
But as to the
objection that prudence makes us no more apt to do what is noble and just, let
us take the matter a little deeper, beginning thus:—
Just as we say that
some people who perform just acts are still not just (for example, those who
carry out the requirements of the law unwillingly, or through ignorance, or for
some ulterior purpose and not for what they are, and yet are actually doing
what is right and all that a good man is bound to do); so, it seems, there is a
state of mind in which a person can perform the various kinds of act in such a
way as to be a good man: that is, when he does them from choice, and for the
sake of the acts themselves. It is virtue that makes the choice correct.
In this last
paragraph Aristotle makes his strongest point. Rather than finding the worth of
virtuous actions to be only in the actions themselves (an externality), he
looks for another dimension of worth and finds it in the consciousness of the
moral agent: “there is a state of mind in which a person can perform the
various kinds of act in such a way as to be a good man.” This “state of mind”
is the crux. But what is this “state”? For Aristotle, it is not some “inner
kindliness” or “sweet and benevolent disposition” - this is a political
philosopher we are dealing with here, after all. So, rather, this
state of mind is not within people by nature but is acquired through
effortful thought.
Aristotle is
suggesting that, without thought (deliberative prudence), individual moral acts
are dry and empty, lacking the existential passion that thinking through these
thoughts adds. You can be
good, but it is better even to think through one’s goodness, to understand it. This is an invisible quality, adding
nothing to one’s goodness externally; but, precisely for the reason that it, in
its immateriality, cannot defend itself, we must be careful not to forget the
worth of its presence. To do so might lead to a facile anti-intellectualism,
the kind which thinks it is doing a favor to morality, love and human
fellowship by rejecting the distracting complications of cold “theorizing”.
This may be a
controversial point, since I know plenty of people who for whom the meaning of
religion and the height of spirituality is love and the struggle after justice,
both through small and big acts. They say, “kindness, benevolence, and
compassion – these don’t need philosophy!”
There is nothing
horribly askew about this. It is true that “knowledge without action is
useless.” Only, I think when philosophy is done right – and I try to be the first to say (at
the cost of exposing my own guilt) that it is often done very poorly, without
the end of living a good life in mind at all – it can add immense value to the
embodied actions of love and compassion; not the same kind of value as action,
of course, but that “invisible value.”
For those of us who
have done serious philosophizing, this is self evident. We only need to be
reminded. At least, I need to be constantly reminded. I am far
too attracted by the quietism of the likes of Wittgenstein, and the various
versions of “anti-philosophy” out there. It is too easy to fall into
self-deprecation when I realize how irrelevant philosophy is to most people in
the world. But, it only takes a little more philosophizing to realize that it
is not philosophy but the hypertrophy of philosophy which is
destructive and life-sapping.
And besides,
philosophy is here to stay. No one can defend themselves against the question
"why don't you philosophize?" without answering
philosophically...
No comments:
Post a Comment