Otto Rank's magnum opus, Art and Artist, was never published in the language in which he wrote it, German. It was translated by an American enthusiast for Rank's thought and published in the U.S., in 1932. On the whole it has received far less attention than it deserves. Forty years after its publication, Ernest Becker celebrated and leaned heavily upon Rank's work in his Pulitzer-winning The Denial of Death—after which Art and Artist promptly receded back into the mists of history. Now, another forty year later, we might hope for another resurgence. This is one reason I am providing a collection of sorted quotes from the book; I have found little online interaction with the text, and I feel that at least the most provoking, time-tested parts of his book deserve to be searchable on google. I have grouped them according to the themes that interested me. These themes are not organizing principles of the book. Actually, it is hard to find any organizing principles in the book—another reason for these grouped quotes.
* * *
Rank’s premise:
-
“A common spiritual root for the meaning and
origin of collective ideologies... I conceived to be the belief in
immortality, and this belief I regarded (if one can say so of any one belief)
as the original ideology, out of which, as it became increasingly untenable,
there arose various others, more securely anchored in reality, but always
animated by the same immortalization tendency… From whatever the artist
achieves by his successful work is in actual fact immortality, a result from
which we need only infer this intention in order to obtain an understanding of
the individual will to art as a personal urge to immortality. In this sense,
however, the feeling of immortality is not only the result of creating but
actually the presupposition on which it rests” (xxvi).
-
“Artistic productivity, not only in the
individual, but probably in the whole development of culture, begins with one’s
own human body and ascends to the creation and artistic formation of a
soul-endowed personality” (355).
-
The creative impulse has been channeled through
art, the motivation for this is a desire for immortality. Art is therefore
motivated by mistaking it as a means for salvation. “The artist does not
create, in the first place, for fame or immortality; his production is to be a
means to achieve actual life, since it helps him to overcome fear” (408-09). “In
him the wheel will have turned full circle, from primitive art, which sought to
raise the physical ego out of nature, to the voluntaristic art of life, which
can accept the psychical ego as a part of the universe. But the condition of
this is the conquest of the fear of life, for that fear has led to the
substitution of artistic production for life, and to the eternalization of the
all-too-mortal ego in a work of art” (430).
The artist says
something of himself with the material of another: “the artist, as a
definite creative individual, uses the art-form that he finds ready to his hand
in order to express a something personal; this personal must therefore be
somehow connected with the prevailing artistic or cultural ideology, since
otherwise he could not make use of them, but it must also differ, since
otherwise he would not need to use them in order to produce something of his
own… The artist not only creates his art, but also uses art in order to create”
(6-7).
Art imitates not
nature, but “soul” – the “mirror of nature” is a low view of art:
-
“The redeeming power of art, that which entitles
it to be regarded aesthetically as beautiful, reside in the way in which it
lends concrete abstract existence to abstract ideas of the soul” (13).
-
“Worrigner was certainly right in denying that
art began with the imitation of nature, or even had this object; but it was
imitation all the same, though in a wider sense” (14).
-
“Art unquestionably serves an end, probably even
serves a variety of ends – but the ends are not concrete and practical, they
are abstract and spiritual” (14).
-
Art
creates and “proves”, not just “illustrates” or “represents” ideas: “religion
used [art] as a means to represent, in objective and concrete form, the
contemporary idea of the soul; but not, so to say, ‘illustratively,’ as if
mankind were too immature to form abstract ideas of the soul. It had to be made
concrete, pictorial, and real, so as to prove
its existence… It is therefore not a defective faculty of abstraction which drives
to the concretization of the soul and its pictorial representation in the god,
but the will to objectify it and thus to impart to it existence, and, what is
more, eternity” (15).
-
“The imitation, however, concerns the unreal,
which later becomes steadily more naturalized and humanized, while the
aimlessness concerns reality – a fact which aesthetics has, strangely enough,
inverted by looking for imitativeness, vis-a-vis
reality, in which domain it has no purpose- and so being led to deny that art
has any aim except that of aesthetic gratification” (96).
-
“Thus, at the very commencement of human
development – then indeed, in far greater measure than subsequently – we have
the unreal element as the decisive factor which led to expression in art. But
if religion is originally unreal, and the (psychologically speaking) equivalent
love-experience at the other end of the scale is predominantly real, art stands
in the middle, realizing the unreal and rendering it concrete. In doing so, it
merely follows a universal law of development… that human development consists
in a continuously progressive concretization of phenomena that were originally
purely ideal or spiritual. In this sense the whole of cultural development is
an artistic, or at least artificial, attempt to objectify human ideologies”
(103).
-
“The essence of art, however, lies precisely in
the concrete representation of the abstract” (415).
The meaning behind
any piece art is egotistical – that is, any given piece of art represents the
creative urge as well as having a specific aesthetic effect: “The tacit
assumption that the artist intended to present the effect he aimed at in its
phenomenal form, and that therefore there were involved in the creation, at
least potentially, the same psychological experiences and psychical processes
as are to be observed in the contemplator of the work and especially in the
aesthetic critic. Without disputing that in some cases the artist does aim at a
definite idea effect in his work, it is certainly not the rule, especially with
the individual work of the creative artist, since here the work of art is
essentially an expression of his personality… While aesthetic pleasure, whether
in the creator in the contemplator, is ultimately a renunciation of the self,
the essence of the creative impulse is exactly opposite tendency towards
assertion of the self” (23).
The neurotic vs.
the artist:
-
“The neurotic, no matter whether productive or
obstructed, suffers fundamentally from the fact that he cannot or will not
accept himself, his own individuality, his own personality. On one hand he
criticizes himself to excess, on the other he idealizes himself to excess,
which means that he makes too great demands on himself and his completeness, so
that failing to attain leads only to more self-criticism. If we take this
thwarted type, as we may do for our purposes, and compare him to the artist, it
is at once clear that the artist is in a sense the antithesis to the
self-critical neurotic type. Not that the artist does not criticize himself,
but by accepting his personality he not only fulfils that for which the
neurotic is striving in vain, but goes far beyond it. The precondition, then,
of the creative personality is not only its acceptance, but its actual
glorification, of itself” (27).
-
The neurotic, on the other hand, is generally
regarded as the weak-willed type, but wrongly so, for his strong will is
exercised upon himself and, indeed, in the main repressively so it does not
show itself… Both are distinguished fundamentally from the average type, who
accepts himself as he is, by their tendency to exercise their volition in
reshaping themselves. There is, however, this difference: that the neurotic, in
this voluntary remaking of his ego, does not get beyond the destructive
preliminary work and is therefore unable to detach the whole creative process
from his own person and transfer it to an ideological abstraction. The
productive artist also begins… with that re-creation of himself which results
in an ideologically constructed ego; this ego is then in a position to shift
the creative will-power from his own person to ideological representations of
that person and thus to render it objective” (41).
-
The
neurotic holds back: “His only thought, one may say, is to save life and life-force, but this saving
brings him no aesthetic pleasure, but neurotic dissatisfaction, because it
dreads every sort of spending, even spending on a plane of illusion. From the
therapy of such cases it has emerged that the neurotic must first learn to live
playfully, illusorily, unreally, on some plane of illusion – first of all on
the inner emotional plane. This is a gift which the artist, as an allied type,
seems to possess from the outset, and in an even higher degree than the average
person possess it. For the artist too is a totalist type that, unlike the
average, cannot live in perpetual ‘partialization,’ but is forced to totalize
every act of life. And on the artistic plane of illusion, in the act of
creating – which is at once appearance and reality, a part and a whole – he
finds it possible to conquer creatively this fundamental human dualism and to
derive pleasure therefrom” (109).
The creative urge
begins with the artist’s self-election of himself as an artist:
-
“The act which we have described as the artist’s
self-appointment as such is in itself a spontaneous expression of the creative
impulse, of which the first manifestation is simply the forming of the
personality itself… but this alone does not suffice to make an artist or a
genius. It is, however, indispensable” (37).
-
“Creativeness lies equally at the root of
artistic production of life experience… the creative impulse itself is manifest
first and chiefly in the personality, which, being thus perpetually made over,
produces art-work and experience in the same way” (38).
-
Art and
will: “I see the creator-impulse as the life impulse made to serve the
individual will” (39).
-
“For the artist impulse to create is a dynamic
factor apart from the content of experience, a will-problem which the artist
solves in a particular way. That is, he is capable of forming the given
art-ideology – whether of the collective kind (style) or the personal
(genuis-idea) – into the substance of his creative will. He employs, so to say,
personal will-power to give form or life to an ideology…” (50).
-
“The creative type nominates itself at once as
an artist… in the artist-type the creative urge is constantly related,
ideologically, to his own ego… whereas the average man uses his calling chiefly
as a means to material existence, and psychically only so far as to enable him
to feel himself a useful member of human society… the artist needs his calling
for his spiritual existence, just as the early cultures of mankind could not
have existed and developed without art… His calling is not a means of
livelihood, but life itself” (371).
-
“always the starting point in the formation of a
biography is the individual’s ideologizing of himself to be an artist, because
thenceforward he must live that ideology, so far as reality allows him to do
so; and so far as it does not, the artist makes for himself the experiences
that he needs, searches for them and gives them forms in the sense of his
ideology. …That in every age the poet’s life should be revalued and re-edited
to suit the ideology of that age is only natural, though this does not exactly
lessen the complexity of the problem” (383).
-
The
creative impulse is the mysterious antecedent: “This impulse [to create],
however, produces both the work and the artist, and ultimately the ideologies
necessary for artistic creation and for the artist’s psychology” (424).
The drive for
coherence and totality, and the artist’s resistance:
-
“The creative impulse in the artist, springing
from the tendency to immortalize himself, is so powerful that he is always
seeking to protect himself against the transient experience, which eats up his
ego. The artist takes refuge, with all his own experience only from the life of
actuality, which for him spells mortality and decay, whereas the experience to which
he has given shape imposes itself on him as a creation, which he in fact seeks
to turn into a work. And although the whole artist-psychology may seem to be
centered on the ‘experience,’ this itself can be explained only through the
creative impulse – which attempts to turn ephemeral life into personal
immortality” (39).
-
“The profoundest source of the artist impulse to
create, which I can only satisfactorily explain to myself as the struggle of
the individual against an inherent striving after totality, which forces him
equally in the direction of a complete surrender to life and complete giving of
himself in production. He has to save himself from this totality by fleeing,
now from the Scylla of life, now from the Charybdis of creation, and his escape
is naturally accomplished only at the cost of continual conflict” (60).
-
“For the artist too is a totalist type that,
unlike the average, cannot live in perpetual ‘partialization,’ but is forced to
totalize every act of life. And on the artistic plane of illusion, in the act
of creating – which is at once appearance and reality, a part and a whole – he
finds it possible to conquer creatively this fundamental human dualism and to
derive pleasure therefrom. For when he creates, the artist uses the whole of
himself without being in danger of losing that self therein, for it is certain
that the work itself, from his point of view, represents only a part of his
ego, although it does in fact represent the whole artist and his personality.
It is just, like every good symbol, a pars
pro toto solution, in which, however, the artist does not go charily with
his life, like the neurotic, but positively spends it as he creates. This again
he does not actually, but essentially—that is, he puts into it his being, his
“soul” as we say—and this then stands for the whole living ego, just as the
abstract soul in primitive and later immortality-beliefs represents not only
the whole individual, but even more than that: his essence, and with it the
essence of man and of humans in general. Once more we find art expressing the
same thing as the abstract-soul concept, only in an objectified form, which we
call beautiful precisely in so far as it is unreal “more than earthly.” For
this very essence of a man, his soul, which the artist puts into his work and
which is represented by it, is found again in the work by the enjoyer, just as
the believer finds his soul in religion or in God, with whom he feels himself
to. be one. It is on this identity of the spiritual, which underlies the concept
of collective religion, and not on a psychological identification with the
artist, that the pleasurable effect of the work of art ultimately depends, and
the effect is, in this sense, one of deliverance. The self-renunciation which
the artist feels when creating is relieved when he finds himself again in his
accomplished work, and the self-renunciation which raises the enjoyer above the
limitations of his individuality becomes, through, not identification, but the
feeling of oneness with the soul living in the work of art, a greater and
higher entity. Thus the will-to-form of the artist gives objective expression,
in his work, to the soul’s tendency to self-eternalization, while the aesthetic
pleasure of the enjoyer is enabled, by his oneness with it, to participate in
this objectivization of immortality. But both of them, in the simultaneous
dissolution of their individuality in a greater whole, enjoy, as high pleasure,
the personal enrichment of that individuality through this feeling of oneness.
They have yielded up their mortal ego for a moment, fearlessly and even
joyfully, to receive it back in the next, the richer for this universal
feeling.” (109-10)
-
“A deep study of neurosis has shown me that a
characteristic quality of both the productive and the thwarted… is an
Over-strong tendency towards totality of experience. The so-called adaptability
of the average man consists in a capacity for an extensive partial experience
such as is demanded by our everyday life, with its many and varied problems.
The non-conforming type tends to concentrate its whole personality, its whole
self, on each detail of experience, however trivial or insignificant; but as
this is not only practically impossible but psychically painful (because its
effect is to bring out fear), this type protects itself from a complete
self-exhaustion by powerful inner restraints. Now, the neurotic stops at this
point in the process, thus cutting himself of from both the world and
experience, and, thus faced with the proposition ‘All or nothing,’ chooses the
nothing. The artist, however, here also, in spite of many difficulties and
struggles, finds a constructive, a middle way:
he avoids the complete loss of himself in life, not by remaining in the
negative attitude, but by living himself out entirely in creative work. This
fact is so obvious that, when we intuitively admire some great work of art, we
say the whole artist is in it and expresses himself in it” (373).
-
Identification:
the struggle for unity: “At the highest level of human personality we have
a process which psycho-analysis calls… identification. This identification is
the cho of an original identity, not merely of child and mother, but of
everything living – witness the reverence of the primitive for animals. In man,
identification aims at re-establishing a lost identity: not an identity which
was lost once and for all, phylogenetically through the differentiation of the
sexes, or ontologically in birth, but an identity which the cosmic process,
which has to be continually surrendered and continually re-established in the
course of self-development. In the attempt at this re-establishment the two
types with which we are dealing, the ‘totalist’ and the ‘partialist’, diverge
fundamentally. The average type of a well-adapted ‘partial’ being can feel
himself as part of a greater whole – in religious communion, social and
vocational grouping, or family feeling – and thus find his identity with the
world. The ‘total type, on the other hand, is set on maintaining himself as a
whole and on absorbing the world as part of himself. In so far the artist and
the neurotic are alike, that in contrast to the average man they have a far
wider, more ‘magic’ feeling of the world, which is gained, however, at the cost
of an egocentric attitude towards it. The neurotic stops at the point where he
includes the world within himself and uses this as a protection against the
real claims of life... but here the paths diverge, since the artist can use
this introverted world not only as a protection but as a material; he is thus
never wholly oppressed by it—though often enough profoundly depressed—but can
penetrate it by and with his own personality and then again thrust it from him
and re-create it from himself” (376-77).
-
The artist
protects and endangers the ego at different moments: “the artist-type, with
his tendency to totality of experience, has an instinct to flee from life into
creation, since there to a certain extent he can be sure of matters remaining
under his own control; but this totality tendency itself, which is
characteristic of the really productive type, in the end takes hold of his
creation also, and this totality of creation then threatens to master the
creative artist as effectually as the totality of experience. In short, the
‘totality function’ of the artist-type in the end makes all productivity,
whether in itself or in a particular work, as much a danger for the creative
ego as was the totality of experience from which he took refuge in his art.
Here the conflict of the artist versus the art becomes a struggle of the artist
against his own creation, against the vehement dynamism of this
totality-tendency which forces him to complete self-surrender in his work”
(385).
The cycle repeats,
stretching for transcendence from mortality and collapsing:
-
“He desires to transform death into life, as it
were, though actually he transforms life into death. For not only does the
created work not go on living; it is, in a sense, dead; both as regards the
material, which renders it almost inorganic, and also spiritually and
psychologically, in that it no longer has any significance for its creator,
once he has produced it. He therefore again takes refuge in life, and again
forms experiences, which for their part represent only mortality – and it is
precisely because they are mortal that he wishes to immortalize them in his
work” (39).
A piece of art
cannot be fully explained by…
-
The style: “the individual artist who employs
this style as a form of expression is something more than a mere representation
of this tendency… ” (xliv).
-
An experience: “The mistake in all modern
psychological biography lies in its attempt to ‘explain’ the artist’s work by
his experience, whereas creation can only be made understandable through the
inner dynamism and its central problems” (49).
-
What inspired it: “the creation of a work of art
cannot be explained even by the reconstruction of an inspirer. Thus the factual
and concrete biography of Michelangelo or Shakespeare does not enable us to
understand their works the better” (57).
The artist’s
default is insecurity:
-
“The fundamental problem is individual
difference, which the ego is inclined to interpret as inferiority unless it can
be proved by achievement to be superiority” (42).
-
The artist’s personality and creative urge
cannot be explained by tracing it back to a sense of inferiority or a lack; it
is, in fact, what creates this lack: by breaking away from the collective the
artist cuts himself off from those very sources of validation.
The “uses” of life:
-
“In general, a strong preponderance of the fear
of life will lead rather to neurotic repression, and the fear of death to
production – that is, perpetuation in the work produced. But the fear of life,
which we all suffer, conditions the problem of experience in the productive type
as in other people, just as the fear of death whips up the neurotic’s
constructive powers. The individual whose life is braked is led thereby to flee
from experience, because he fears that he will become completely absorbed in it
– which would mean death – and so is bound up with fear. Unlike, the productive
type, who strives to be deathless through his work, the neurotic does not seek
immortality in any clearly defined sense, but in primitive fashion as a naïve
saving or accumulation of actual life. But even the individualist artist-type
must sacrifice both life and experience to make art out of them. Thus we see
that what the artist needs for true creative art in addition to his technique
and a definite ideology is life in one form or another; and the two artist-types differ essentially
in the source from which they take this life that is so essential to
production. The Classical type, who is possibly poorer within, but nearer
to life, and himself more vital, takes it from without: that is, he creates immortal
work from mortal life without necessarily having first transformed it into
personal experience as is the case with the Romantic. For, to the Romantic,
experience of his own appears to be an essential preliminary to productivity,
although he does not use this experience for the enrichment of his own
personality, but to economize the personal experiences, the burden of which he
would fain escape. Thus the one artist-type constantly makes use of other
life than his own – in fact, nature – for the purpose of creating, while the
other can create only by perpetually sacrificing his own life… From the
spiritual point of view the work of the Classicit, more or less naturalistic,
artist is essentially partial, and the work of the Romantic, produced from
within, total. This totality-type spends itself perpetually in creative work
without absorbing very much of life, while the partial type has continually to
absorb life so that he may throw it off again in his work… [to] save the
artist from having to give himself… The real artist regards his work as more
important than the whole of life and experience, which are but a means to
production – almost, indeed, a by-product of it. This refers, however, to the
Classical type only, for to the Romantic type his personal ego and his
experience are more important than, or as important as, his work; sometimes,
indeed, production may be simply a means to life, just as to the other type
experience is but a means to production…” (48-49).
-
The problem of justification: “The primitive
artist-type finds his justification in the work itself; the Classical justifies
the work by his life, but the Romantic must justify both life and experience by
his work and, further, must have a witness of his life to justify his
production” (50-51).
Creating ideals:
“Experience, and still more the whole attitude towards life, grows out of the
struggle to create and so reduces the problem of experience to the problem of
creativity. For the extent to which the artist succeeds in actualizing his
love-ideal, in the service of his own self-immortalization, is of minor
importance compared with the basic attitude that his work discloses – namely,
one originating in dissatisfaction with artist creation and so urging the
creator in some form or other towards life – that is, towards the actual
experiencing of his fundamental self. In any case his impulse to form man in
his own image or in the image of his ideal inevitably brings him into conflict
with real life and its conditions… Now, a certain measure of conflict is, of
course, necessary to creative work, and this conflict is, in fact, one of the
fields in which na artist displays his greatness, or, psychologically speaking,
the strength of his creative will-power. By means of it he is able to work off
a certain measure of his inner conflict in his art without entirely sacrificing
the realities of life or coming into factual conflict with them. In any case,
the destructive results of this ensemble of realities upon the neurotic, as we
are able to observe them in his neurosis, show that what distinguishes him from
the artist is that the latter constructively applies his will-power to in the
service of ideological creation. A certain type of artist… will learn to deal
with his experiences and conflicts economically and in the end wisely, while
another type exhausts his strength in chasing after stimulating experiences so
that his conflict does not come out in production. For the artist himself the
fact that he creates is more
immediately important than what he
produces” (58).
Attitudes to life:
“Primitive art looks beyond individual, mortal life towards an everlasting
soul. And the essence of Classical art lies in the fact that it renders life
itself everlasting – that is, tries to conserve the actual man as he is and
lives – the very thing that the primitive Egyptian sought to do by
mummification… Modern art, with its dynamics of expression, differs from both
these style-forms; neither starts from an abstract of the living nor aims at an
ideal conservation of it, buts its style-form consists in a vivification of the
essence of the actual. This can, however, only be achieved at the cost of real
life. The three art-ideologies… are based therefore on varying attitudes to
life itself, and these attitudes, although determined by the prevailing collective
ideology, will still be found to vary in the different individuals of the same
epoch” (71).
Art vs. Life:
-
“On the other hand, creativity itself is, of
course, a special form of experience and one peculiar to the artist, and all
depends in the last resort upon whether the individual is capable of restoring
harmony, or at least a temporary balance, between the two forms of experience -
artistic and vital - and to what extent he succeeds. This does not by any means
signify that the person who better adapts himself to, or succeeds in, life
must-needs be the better artist. In this respect Goethe forms a single
exception in the whole long line of really great men whose lives have been
swallowed whole by their work. Croce maintains that this was the case even with
Goethe, but in reality the man Goethe has come to be more important to us than
his work, which we are inclined to regard as more interesting from a
psycho-biographical than from a purely artistic standpoint. Goethe himself
looked upon his works as “fragments of one great confession,” as “life’s
traces,” and it looks as if this had been more or less consciously the artist’s
general attitude towards his work. His work is not only his particular
expression of life: it both serves him and helps him to live, and his worth as
an artist comes second - or even plays no special part at all. A mediocre work,
acceptable only to a small circle, may yet satisfy the artist more and mean
more to him than the undying world-fame of a poem that has grown into a folk-song,
the author of which most people are quite at a loss to name.” (82).
-
“If Goethe’s importance lies rather in his
representing the purely Classical ideal, as against the personal
artist-ideology of Romanticism, than in his actual creative work, he is perhaps
the first example—and at the same time the highest possible type—of the poet
who becomes a universal genius. Also, in our own day, such a type could express
himself as an essayist, a cultural critic, or a first-class journalist. As we
have already pointed out, our modern author has become conscious of the
personal art-ideology that is within him; but the first result of the process
has been to project this intuitively recognized artist-ideology on to the
history of art and to misinterpret the whole of its development in the light of
its latest phase” (83).
-
“the poet also, and the artist in general,
sacrifices his life to gain immortality. How far this is a necessary
precondition of artistic production, for whose purpose life must be spent, and
how far it is a more or less conscious self-sacrifice of the man to his work,
is one of the deepest problems in the whole psychology of productivity” (289).
-
“Since Renaissance days, there can be no doubt
that the great works of art were bought at the cost of ordinary living” (429).
Sex-impulse: “The
will, conscious or unconscious, will always be the expression of the
individual, the indivisible single being while sexuality represents something
shared, something generic which is harmonious with the individually—willed only
in the human love-experience and is otherwise in perpetual conflict with it. In
art this conflict is won in a different way; though closely akin to the
individual conquest in love and the collective conquest in religion, it is
differentiated from both by a specific element which we may broadly call the aesthetic.
We shall deal with the peculiar qualities which this consists of in our next
section. In closing this section we need only say, without particularizing,
that the artistic solution of this original dualism is not merely
psychological, but appears, as regards its evolutionary history, to lie between
the religious and the erotic solutions. The religious solution is at bottom
collective; that is, the individual is delivered from his isolation and becomes
part of a greater and higher whole—not in the biological- generic sense, but
through his spiritual ideology, by becoming one with God. In the
love-experience, which becomes possible only at a stage of fully developed
individualism, we see this spiritual process objectified: God, as representing
the idealized self, is found in the beloved, and, with the sense of union, the
individuality seems to be exalted and intensified, lost, and yet enriched.
Finally, in art, which has developed out of the collective consolation-ideology
of religion and at whose further limit we find the Romantic artist striving
after the complete love-experience, the individuality-conflict is solved in
that the ego, seeking at once isolation and union, creates, as it were, a
private religion for itself, which not only expresses the collective spirit of
the epoch, but produces a new ideology—the artistic—which for the bulk of them
takes the place of religion. True, this happens only at the summit of
individual “artist’s art,” where there is deification of the genius-concept and
an adoration of works of art which is comparable only to the worship of statues
of gods, though they already represent mere men. Before this, art is still -
particularly in its Classical period - an individual working-out of the forces
of which religions are made. These forces then become concentrated in the
single creative individual, whereas before they animated a whole community. The
works of these peak periods of artistic production manifest in their development
the individualized religion-forming forces which finally return, by way of
Romantic love-experience, to their origin, which is the personal craving for
immortality of the ego. All three ideologies, however—the collective-religious,
the social-artistic, and the individual-erotic—lift the individual above the
biological life-plane of reality—in which only the sexual immortality of
propagation counteracts the individual isolation—on a higher, supernatural,
super-real, or super-individual sphere wherein reigns an ideal collectivity
that is created by individual intention and may at any time be altered at
will.” (85-87)
Energy: “Art,
like play, passes from the condition of being a compulsory activity necessary
for life into the realm of freedom even if (again as in play) this liberation
can never be wholly successful. Hence we have the explanation of the two types
of artist: that which creates from an inner need and that which does so from an
inner surplus. But in both cases the greatest part of creative force can
come only from an excess that arises during and out of the actual creation,
just as in play the playing itself is needed to liberate the energy in the
individual” (328).
Life vs. truth:
“When it is still tied to nature, the ceremony is more or less an imitation
thereof, whereas the freedom of play tends rather towards stylization the one
being, even in the deeper sense, nearer to truth, and the other to beauty. When
I say ‘in the deeper sense,’ I mean that man’s acceptance of his dependence on
nature is more honest, while freedom-ideology, beyond a certain point, presumes
the negation of that dependence and is therefore, also in a deeper sense,
dishonest. This fundamental dishonesty towards nature then comes out as the
consciousness of guilt, which we see active in every process of art, and which
is not wholly absent from play. This feeling of guilt, of human hybris… also
allows neither play nor the exercise of art to rise wholly from compulsion to
freedom; nay, the more strongly man feels his freedom and his independence, the
more intense on the other hand is the consciousness of guilt, which appears in
the individual partly restrictive, partly creative, but in the community is
accompanied by the gradual growth and formation of another ideology, that of
truth, which acts paralysingly on the freedom of the ideology of beauty… This
is the profound reason for Plato’s exclusion of artists from his ideal
republic; for in their extreme type, the poet, he saw the truth-falsifying
element, which his scientific ideologism condemned as lying ” (328-29).
Art denies
dependence: “The truth of the dependence of man on nature, which play and
art deny, reappears out of this guilt-feeling as the impulse to scientific
knowledge” (330).
Beauty vs. Truth:
-
“This conflict between the ideologies of truth
and beauty, which only worked its way into the full consciousness of mankind in
Greece, is actually as old as humanity itself, because in last analysis the
root of it is the dualism between mortality and immortality. For, in our view,
even the most primitive art consists in the attempt to make the abstract idea
of the soul “true” by making it concrete; that is, aesthetically satisfying,
or, in other words, beautiful. The question whether primitive likenesses were
portraits or of symbolic character could therefore become prominent in
art-history only as and when truth and beauty fell apart, as they have
increasingly done in the European spiritual culture from the time of the Greeks
onwards. For primitive artists the question was quite meaningless, for their
truth was not realistic, but spiritual” (334).
-
“the artistic and scientific ideologies of the
beautiful (that is, the immortal) and of the true (that is, the mortal soul)” (347-48).
Consciousness as
conquest (through will-to-form):
-
“If we take modern art as a comparison ready to
hand, we find that both, form as well as content, are becoming more and more
individually subjective, and that the impulse to create, which is still
fundamentally the same, is more and more a matter of consciousness in the
artist. But there is a certain limit to subjectivity which the most individual
of artists cannot pass; and for two reasons: because the creative impulse,
which is fundamentally always the same, implies a similar principle of form,
or, better, impulse to form: and secondly because, if the work is to have some
general influence, it must manipulate some collective content of general human
significance. Thus, subjectively, there does exist in the artist the creative
impulse which in the individual, as arising from the conflict between the lower
and the higher self, corresponds to what in the history of culture we have
traced as a gradual defeat of the animal by the spiritual principle. This
impulse includes those elements of the conflict which strive towards the
voluntary control and domination of the lower by the higher self; the actual
victory comes, in art, from the will-like impulse to form, which at first aims
at no more than a cessation of the conflict by delimiting and ordering it.
This impulse to form, and at first finds, collective traditional forms, which
had been produced by similar conflicts in the course of cultural development,
and which in many cases carry with them their particular content. These
collectively transmitted or dominant forms constitute what in their totality we
call style, by accepting which (in whatever degree) the artist does subject
himself to a principle outside his individual self. And though it may be collective,
it is yet a man-created collectivity, and not one prescribed by nature. Here
too our earlier formulation of the imitation-ideology fits into its place, for
while we allowed imitation its full importance, we showed besides that it is no
matter of simply copying nature, but of representing nature as already altered
or interpreted by man in his own sense (macrocosm-microcosm)” (360).
-
“In his inner conflict, then, which corresponds
potentially to that of earlier cultures, he looks instinctively later, perhaps,
consciously for collective forms to justify and to liberate himself, but he
also looks for a collective (material) content, so that he may achieve
simultaneously personal freedom and collective effect” (361).
-
Victory
over the ego: “The victory is always, at bottom and in some form, won over
a part of one’s own ego. We may remark here that every production of a
significant artist, in whatever form, and of whatever content, always reflects
more or less clearly this process of self-liberation and reveals the battle of
the artist against the art which expresses a now surmounted phase of the
development of his ego. In some artists the representation of a process of
personal development seems to be the chief aim of their work… This process of
the increasing extension of consciousness in humanity, which psycho-analysis
has fostered so enormously in the last decades… was prophesied by me… as likely
to be the beginning of a decay art” (375).
“The struggle of the artist against art is really only an
ideologized continuation of the individual struggle against the collective”
(372).
Creation is the
justification for creation:
-
“As the artist, during this process of
liberation from the ideology, has to include in what he surrenders the person
or persons who were connected with it, he has to justify this action, which is
usually done by magnification. That is, he will either really create something
greater, in order to justify his action, or in the effort create this greater
he will be impeded by a still more enhanced feeling of guilt” (380).
-
“This type… has its opposite in another type of
artist, who not only gives and fulfills himself in every work, but whose whole
production is one vast justification of his impulse to create” (381).
Conflict with ideology:
“This feeling of the poet that he is the mouthpiece of his age or, for that
matter, of all humanity, explains not only why he has to ascribe his work to a
Muse and thus connect it with his personal life and give it concrete form; it
also throws a light on the fact that, and the degree to which, the art-ideology
affects the poet’s life. There is thus an influence of personal experience on
creation and a reciprocal influence of creation on experience, which not only
drives the artist externally to a Bohemian existence, but makes his inner life
characterologically a picture of his art-ideology and thus once more calls
forth the individual self in protest against this domination by that ideology”
(382).
Two tendencies of
the artist:
-
“the one which wishes to eternalize itself in
artistic creation, the other which wants to spend itself in ordinary life”
(395).
-
“Because of its ‘totality-tendency,’ the
creative type is inclined, in this struggle between life and creation, to give
up the one wholly in favour of the other, and this naturally intensifies the
conflict rather than solves it” (395).
The artist and his
justification for art:
-
“The artist does not create, in the first
place, for fame or immortality; his production is to be a means to achieve
actual life, since it helps him to overcome fear. But he cannot get out of
the bypath he has once trodden, which was to lead him back by means of his work
to life. He is thus more and more deeply entangled in his creative dynamism,
which receives its seal in success and fame” (408-09).
-
Self-assertion
and self-surrender: “But along with all these expressions of the opposition
of the artist to art-ideology, to the dynamism of creation and the final
absorption of his individual immortality by the community, there must exist
other, and even stronger, tendencies of surrender, self-renunciation, and
self-sacrifice. These seem to be just as necessary for the artist as the
tendencies of self-assertion and self-eternalization; and, indeed, we have had
to assume that what is perhaps the most decisive part of creative dynamism
originates in this conflict of opposing tendencies and their settlement in the
harmony of the work. This conflict between self-assertion and self-surrender is
a normal phenomenon in human psychical life, which in the artist is
extraordinarily intensified and reaches gigantic, one might say macrocosmic
heights. As the strong creative personality is driven to destroy a pre-existing
ideology, instead of a mere individual, as his “building-sacrifice” before he may
eternalize himself in a new one, the conflict between surrender and assertion,
which otherwise takes place in relation to a person, is here manifested with
society and its whole order as the player on the other side” (409).
-
“The individual may, by his nomination to be an
artist, have asserted his independence of the human community and rooted
himself in self-sufficient isolation; but ultimately he is driven by the work
he has autonomously produced to surrender again to that community. This
creative self-sufficingness which generates the work out of oneself alone…”
(409).
-
“I believe we have here a deliberate denial of
all dependence…The artist therefore has to give himself the more and more
intensively and exhaustively in his work because he has created it the more independently
of others” (410).
-
Justification
through proof of the unreal: “Not only does his work become the most
concrete proof that the individual can live on in spirit for centuries; but the
last sections have shown us how the artist is under a sort of organic
compulsion to transform his art-ideology into experience. In this he makes
reality of the unreal to just the extent that it represents the concretization
of the soul-concept in the work. In other words, the artist must live his
ideology so that he, as well as others, may believe in it as true; on the
other hand, this ideological experience acts both as a means to make artistic
productivity possible and as a means to live a real life. For we have seen that
the basic conflict of the creative personality is that between his desire to
live a natural life in an ordinary sense and the need to produce
ideologically—which corresponds socially to that between individuality and
collectivity and biologically to that between the ego and the genus. Whereas
the average man largely subordinates himself, both socially and biologically,
to the collective, and the neurotic shuts himself deliberately off from both,
the productive type finds a middle way, which is expressed in ideological
experience and personal creativity. But since the artist must live as a human
being and yet feels compelled to make this transitory life eternal in an
intransient work, a compromise is set up between ideologized life and an
individualized creativity—a balance which is difficult, impermanent, and in all
circumstances painful, since creation tends to experience, and experience again
cries out for artistic form” (416).
-
Free from
the need to justify: “An artist who feels that he is driven into creating
by an external deprivation and who is then again obstructed by a longing for
life can rise above these conflicts to a renunciant view of life which
recognizes that it is not only impossible but perilous to live out life to the
full and can, willingly and affirmatively, accept the limitations that appear
in the form of moral conventions and artistic standards, not merely as such,
but as protective measures against a premature and complete exhaustion of the
individual. This means the end of all doubt as to whether he is to dedicate his
whole life to art or send art to perdition and simply live; also of the
question whether he is live a Bohemian life in accordance with his ideology or
live an ordinary life in despite of his art; and in the end his creativity is
not only made richer and deeper by this renunciatory attitude, but is freed from the need to justify one or the
other mode of life” (417).
The development of
personality:
-
“But the more conscious the creative process
becomes in the artist, the more the creative tendency is imperceptibly and unnoticed
being pushed back from the work to the artist himself from whom it originated.
Only, primitively this self-creative tendency showed itself, as we saw,
corporeally in body-ornament, whereas in the modern artist it ends with the
psychical will-to-experience, his own art-ideology in full. This is, of course,
impossible and brings the artist into all the conflicts – which we may describe
as neurotic, but which are not any the more intelligible for being so called.
For these difficulties of the creative type show also that his true tendency is
always towards actual life; as is shown also in the so-called realism or verism
of modern art. This therefore discloses itself as the counterpart to the
tendency, which has been mentioned earlier, to mould life in accordance with an
artistic ideology, since the idea is now that art is to be made wholly true to
life. But in this wise the boundaries between art and life are obliterated;
each is to replace the other whereas formerly each complemented the other. In both
spheres the movement from art to life is clear; but the creative men of our
time are not capable of going the whole way and accepting the development of
their personality as the truly creative problem. What hinders them is the same
individual feeling of guilt which in earlier times was able, owing to the
counter-force of religious submissiveness, to work itself out creatively, but
nowadays limits both complete artistic creation and complete
personality-development. For artistic creation has, in the course of its
development, changed from a means for the furtherance of the culture of the
community into a means for the construction of personality” (425).
-
“I feel that the modern artist has to buy his
success too dearly, since he feels either like a believer among unbelievers or
like the founder of a new religion who is persecuted and scorned by the members
of the old religion” (427).
-
“it is a fatal confusion to assume that every
strong personality must express itself artistically if it is to develop” (427).
-
“Art does not, after a point, favour the
personality, but impedes it, since it forces on the artist a professional
ideology which more and more penetrates the human self and finally absorbs it…
The two masters whom the artist has to serve at the same time, a self-confident
productivity and a life of sacrifice, are less and less reconcilable, so that
art and life are both dissatisfying, or, rather, the individual attains
neither, because he is not satisfied with one and cannot attain both” (428).
Art and salvation:
-
“If he seeks his salvation in artist creation
instead of in the development of his own personality, it is because he is still
in the toils of old art-ideologies” (430).
-
“In him the wheel will have turned full circle,
from primitive art, which sought to raise the physical ego out of nature, to
the voluntaristic art of life, which can accept the psychical ego as a part of
the universe. But the condition of this is the conquest of the fear of life,
for that fear has led to the substitution of artistic production for life, and
to the eternalization of the all-too-mortal ego in a work of art. For the
artistic individual has lived in art-creation instead of actual life, letting
his work live or die on its own account, and has never wholly surrendered
himself to life. In place of his own self the artist puts his objectified ego
into his work, but though he does not save his subjective mortal ego from
death, he yet withdraws himself from real life. And the creative type who can
renounce this protection by art and can devote his whole creative force to life
and the formation of life will be the first representative of the new human
type, and in return for this renunciation will enjoy, in personality-creation
and expression, a greater happiness” (430-31).
I like your presentation of Art and Artist. You should see if you can get it posted on Wikipedia.
ReplyDeletethank you so much for this! this is very helpful for a project I'm working on, I'm writing a fantasy graphic novel and making a presentation of its theoretical framework for my senior project. I have a six-feet-high stack of things to read along a bunch of different tangents and this is a great orientation to some thought provoking ideas!
ReplyDeleteThank you, Patrick
ReplyDeleteMuch needed. Cheers.
ReplyDeleteA final comment, there is an organizing principle to this work, although the many investigations and applications only can be described with multiple quotes.
ReplyDelete“Here we may state, more definitely than we have as yet, that the main task of this book is to expound the development and change in meaning of art-forms from similar changes in the idea of the soul, which decides the development of personality, even as it is itself influenced thereby.”
https://staff.washington.edu/mounce/
Your phenomenal undertaking (just now) came to my attention as I am immersed in some relevant vocational researches. It's a great gift -- as you suggest -- resonant with our humankind collective's presently sweeping psycho-cultural paradigm's chaotic explosion. (I will return from studying for further comment). Thank you
ReplyDelete